European Nuclear Society
e-news Issue 7 Winter 2005
http://www.euronuclear.org/library/public/enews/ebulletinwinter2005/listening.htm

TAPPING UNUSUAL QUARTERS

Cognitive Dissonance and the Nuclear Debate

The concept of cognitive dissonance was introduced by Leon Festinger in a book titled A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance published in 1957, almost fifty years ago. The focus of this book was on a psychological condition that has certainly been experienced by all of us: receiving a piece of information that contradicts previously-held beliefs. Cognitive dissonance is the state arising from the realisation that one is now faced with an inconsistency in one’s system of beliefs. How serious is the feeling of unease resulting from cognitive dissonance and what individuals do to remove this feeling are the main subjects of interest of this book and of a lot of ensuing research. One example will at the same time make the concept clearer and show what it can be used for. Let us


Leon Festinger

consider a customer who purchases, say, an electric appliance. This very act is liable to arouse dissonance: the negative aspects of the action taken, as well as the positive aspects of alternatives (not purchasing, or purchasing something else) is dissonant with the decision. The purchaser will have to do something to reduce the ensuing psychological discomfort. In this context, one would conjecture that the effort exerted to reduce the tension should be proportional to the discomfort experienced1. Many experiments designed to investigate such situations

in controlled conditions have confirmed this hypothesis2. The concept of cognitive dissonance does not just apply to the understanding of individual reactions in everyday situations. It can also be used to analyse cases where the dissonance comes from a discrepancy between an accepted theory and the occurrence of new facts that seem to give the lie to the said theory. It can be confidently predicted that, here also, cognitive dissonance reduction mechanisms will come into play.

These ideas can be usefully applied to the controversy surrounding the peaceful use of nuclear energy. Both the supporters and the critics of nuclear energy have encountered states of cognitive dissonance. Let us call them Pronukes and Antinukes respectively for short and give two examples:

Is one entitled to see in the responses of both parties mere attempts to reduce their respective states of cognitive dissonance? Third parties could be tempted to say yes and hence consider that the Pronukes' and Antinukes' positions are actually symmetrical. Such an attitude would apparently be justified as it would conveniently explain why the nuclear controversy has been inconclusive for so long.

One additional consideration can help to clarify the issue raised above. When an individual (or a group) is faced with a discrepancy between theory and observations, two options are available. One can either adjust/reject the theory to take account of the new observations or question the validity of the said observations because they do not fit the theory. In principle, both options have some value; they are complementary and in their judicious use resides the essence of scientific progress. In practice, how have the Pronukes and Antinukes dealt with their respective problems? By and large, the Pronukes have adjusted their theories and the Antinukes have questioned the observations. To come back to the examples provided above,


Three Mile Island


Chernobyl

These two examples are typical of what the two parties usually do. On the one hand, the Pronukes adjust their theories most of the time through the implementation of practical measures; additional examples are Generation III reactors, the Generation IV project, the study of ageing mechanisms, etc. In one area at least, economics, the Pronukes' attack has been two-pronged: new reactor designs feature lower costs and the way costs are computed has evolved to take a fuller account of the externalities. On the other hand, the Antinukes systematically question the validity of figures or observations that do not support their basic tenets. They have done so regarding the economics of nuclear energy, uranium reserves, the amount of CO2 generated by nuclear power plants, the environmental impact of reprocessing. They have done so each time a quantitative assessment relating to nuclear energy was publicised. What should raise eyebrows is that they always manage to counter the assessments made by the Pronukes. No human being is right all the time. This is where the purported symmetry breaks down: the Pronukes demonstrate their human nature occasionally, while the Antinukes never go wrong.

Oh, by the way, there's one thing I almost forgot to mention. The philosophy of knowledge has given names to the two approaches for dealing with discrepancies between theory and observations: adjusting theory to facts is called the critical approach and questioning the facts that do not support the theory is called the dogmatic approach.

1 This, by the way, is the reason why seasoned sales attendants will always endorse your choice whenever they notice that the decision was difficult.
2 See for instance the first chapter of Cognitive Dissonance: Progress on a Pivotal Theory in Social Psychology, edited by Eddie Harmon-Jones and Judson Mills, APA Books.
3 For risk compendia, see ENS NEWS issue no 2, autumn 2003.


© European Nuclear Society, 2005