A question of logic
by Andrew Teller
The readers of ENS News who have followed this
column might have noticed that its author is sometimes at pains
to point out flaws in the reasoning of the anti-nuclear argument.
If the said readers are somewhat sceptical, they might have also
realised that highlighting the falsity of a piece of reasoning
does not prove the falsity of the conclusion derived. They would
be right. Anybody can reach a valid conclusion despite failures
in one’s analysis of the question at hand. The assumption
that the opponents of nuclear energy might be right at the end
of the day despite the mistakes they regularly pile up in their
reasoning cannot be lightly dismissed. Why is it then that I
have been so far satisfied with exposing the shortcomings of
the arguments put forward by the critics of nuclear energy? The
answer to this question is not as obvious as one could be tempted
to believe.
To understand why, we must first revert to the
basic rules of logic and more precisely to the proper use of
the logical operator named implication. This operator, which
has been known about since the times of Aristotle at least, encapsulates
the fundamental dissymmetry between correct and false reasoning.
What it says in a nutshell is that true (or valid) and false
(or invalid) premises behave differently as to the conclusions
that can be derived from them: deriving a true conclusion from
a true premise yields a true proposition while deriving a false
conclusion from a true premise yields a false proposition. On
the other hand, false premises can lead equally well to true
or false conclusions. This is a pity. Life would be so much easier
if false premises always led to false conclusions. If this were
the case, maths teachers would have much less work with exams:
they would just look at the answers of their students without
bothering to go into the nitty-gritty of the calculations since
a valid conclusion would stem only from a valid derivation. But
this not being the case, they must also inspect the premises
in order to confirm that the correct answer given by the student
was indeed legitimately obtained, i.e. not reached by pure chance.
We have so confirmed that spotting a flaw in
an argument does not mean that its conclusion is invalid. But
we have also shown that it does not mean that it is valid either.
Identifying a shortcoming does not therefore kill the argument
but is a clear indication that the intended point remains to
be made. This is much less than what the supporters of nuclear
energy would like, but certainly more than its opponents hoped
for. Now let us not delude ourselves: despite our concern for
accuracy, we supporters of nuclear energy also make mistakes.
When we make use of an invalid premise, the conclusion derived
from it does not fall through but remains to be proven. This
state of affairs mirrors the one described above: this is much
less than what we would like, but certainly more than our opponents
hope for.
At this point, the latter could try to seek
support from Hans Jonas, the German philosopher whose thinking
is at the root of the precautionary principle. They could try
to claim that the potential consequences of the use of nuclear
energy are so dire that it is preferable to consider their arguments
valid even when they are not warranted by a watertight derivation.
I am not aware that H. Jonas ever considered contravening the
rules of logic; his main proposal was that adverse consequences
be systematically given precedence over favourable ones. It can
be easily imagined however that an enthusiastic interpretation
of his recommendation could invite some to extend the process
to bending the rules of logic itself. But this would not do.
Flouting the rules of logic is equivalent to giving up the use
of reason altogether in the decision process. The argumentation
of the anti-nuclear could and would then boil down to claiming
that “nuclear energy is bad because it is bad”. This
is not however what they are doing. I infer from this fact that
they implicitly accept the principle that any piece of reasoning
must obey the rules of logic, in which case there is no escape
from the fact their points remain to be made in all cases where
there is a mistake in the way they try to make it.
The conclusion of this short analysis is that the inconclusive
state of the debate between supporters and opponents of nuclear
energy is to be put down to the strange behaviour of the logical
implication: it leaves the protagonists all too often in a state
of doubt and leads to certainty only in very few instances.
|